Grue and bleen are examples of logical
predicates coined by Nelson Goodman in Fact, Fiction, and Forecast to
illustrate the "new riddle of induction". These predicates are
unusual because their application is time-dependent; many have tried to solve
the new riddle on those terms, but Hilary Putnam and others have argued such
time-dependency depends on the language adopted, and in some languages it is
equally true for natural-sounding predicates such as "green." For
Goodman they illustrate the problem of projectible predicates and ultimately,
which empirical generalizations are law-like and which are not. Goodman's
construction and use of grue and bleen illustrates how philosophers use simple
examples in conceptual analysis.
Grue and bleen defined
Goodman defined grue relative to an
arbitrary but fixed time t as follows: An object is grue if and only if it is
observed before t and is green, or else is not so observed and is blue. An
object is bleen if and only if it is observed before t and is blue, or else is
not so observed and is green.
To understand the problem Goodman posed, it
is helpful to imagine some arbitrary future time t, say January 1, 2028. For
all green things we observe up to time t, such as emeralds and well-watered
grass, both the predicates green and grue apply. Likewise for all blue things
we observe up to time t, such as bluebirds or blue flowers, both the predicates
blue and bleen apply. On January 2, 2028, however, emeralds and well-watered
grass are bleen and bluebirds or blue flowers are grue. Clearly, the predicates
grue and bleen are not the kinds of predicates we use in everyday life or in
science, but the problem is that they apply in just the same way as the
predicates green and blue up until some future time t. From our current
perspective (i.e., before time t), how can we say which predicates are more
projectible into the future: green and blue or grue and bleen?
The new riddle of induction
In this section, Goodman's new riddle of
induction is outlined in order to set the context for his introduction of the
predicates grue and bleen and thereby illustrate their philosophical
importance.
The old problem of induction and its
dissolution
Goodman poses Hume's problem of induction
as a problem of the validity of the predictions we make. Since predictions are
about what has yet to be observed and because there is no necessary connection
between what has been observed and what will be observed, what is the
justification for the predictions we make? We cannot use deductive logic to
infer predictions about future observations based on past observations because
there are no valid rules of deductive logic for such inferences. Hume's answer
was that our observations of one kind of event following another kind of event
result in our minds forming habits of regularity (i.e., associating one kind of
event with another kind). The predictions we make are then based on these
regularities or habits of mind we have formed.
Goodman takes Hume's answer to be a serious
one. He rejects other philosophers' objection that Hume is merely explaining
the origin of our predictions and not their justification. His view is that
Hume has identified something deeper. To illustrate this, Goodman turns to the
problem of justifying a system of rules of deduction. For Goodman, the validity
of a deductive system is justified by its conformity to good deductive
practice. The justification of rules of a deductive system depends on our
judgements about whether to reject or accept specific deductive inferences.
Thus, for Goodman, the problem of induction dissolves into the same problem as
justifying a deductive system and while, according to Goodman, Hume was on the
right track with habits of mind, the problem is more complex than Hume
realized.
In the context of justifying rules of
induction, this becomes the problem of confirmation of generalizations for
Goodman. However, the confirmation is not a problem of justification but instead
it is a problem of precisely defining how evidence confirms generalizations. It
is with this turn that grue and bleen have their philosophical role in
Goodman's view of induction.
Projectible predicates
The new riddle of induction, for Goodman,
rests on our ability to distinguish lawlike from non-lawlike generalizations.
Lawlike generalizations are capable of confirmation while non-lawlike
generalizations are not. Lawlike generalizations are required for making
predictions. Using examples from Goodman, the generalization that all copper
conducts electricity is capable of confirmation by a particular piece of copper
whereas the generalization that all men in a given room are third sons is not
lawlike but accidental. The generalization that all copper conducts electricity
is a basis for predicting that this piece of copper will conduct electricity.
The generalization that all men in a given room are third sons, however, is not
a basis for predicting that a given man in that room is a third son.
What then makes some generalizations
lawlike and others accidental? This, for Goodman, becomes a problem of
determining which predicates are projectible (i.e., can be used in lawlike
generalizations that serve as predictions) and which are not. Goodman argues
that this is where the fundamental problem lies. This problem, known as
Goodman's paradox, is as follows. Consider the evidence that all emeralds
examined thus far have been green. This leads us to conclude (by induction)
that all future emeralds will be green. However, whether this prediction is
lawlike or not depends on the predicates used in this prediction. Goodman
observed that (assuming t has yet to pass) it is equally true that every
emerald that has been observed is grue. Thus, by the same evidence we can
conclude that all future emeralds will be grue. The new problem of induction
becomes one of distinguishing projectible predicates such as green and blue
from non-projectible predicates such as grue and bleen.
Hume, Goodman argues, missed this problem.
We do not, by habit, form generalizations from all associations of events we
have observed but only some of them. All past observed emeralds were green, and
we formed a habit of thinking the next emerald will be green, but they were
equally grue, and we do not form habits concerning grueness. Lawlike
predictions (or projections) ultimately are distinguishable by the predicates
we use. Goodman's solution is to argue that lawlike predictions are based on
projectible predicates such as green and blue and not on non-projectible
predicates such as grue and bleen and what makes predicates projectible is
their entrenchment, which depends on their successful past projections. Thus,
grue and bleen function in Goodman's arguments to both illustrate the new
riddle of induction and to illustrate the distinction between projectible and
non-projectible predicates via their relative entrenchment.
Responses
The most obvious response is to point to
the artificially disjunctive definition of grue. The notion of predicate entrenchment
is not required. Goodman, however, noted that this move will not work. If we
take grue and bleen as primitive predicates, we can define green as "grue
if first observed before t and bleen otherwise", and likewise for blue. To
deny the acceptability of this disjunctive definition of green would be to beg
the question.
Another proposed resolution of the paradox
(which Goodman addresses and rejects) that does not require predicate
entrenchment is that "x is grue" is not solely a predicate of x, but
of x and a time t—we can know that an object is green without knowing the time
t, but we cannot know that it is grue. If this is the case, we should not
expect "x is grue" to remain true when the time changes. However, one
might ask why "x is green" is not considered a predicate of a
particular time t—the more common definition of green does not require any
mention of a time t, but the definition grue does. As we have just seen, this
response also begs the question because blue can be defined in terms of grue and
bleen, which explicitly refer to time.
Swinburne
Richard Swinburne gets past the objection
that green may be redefined in terms of grue and bleen by making a distinction
based on how we test for the applicability of a predicate in a particular case.
He distinguishes between qualitative and locational predicates. Qualitative
predicates, like green, can be assessed without knowing the spatial or temporal
relation of x to a particular time, place or event. Locational predicates, like
grue, cannot be assessed without knowing the spatial or temporal relation of x
to a particular time, place or event, in this case whether x is being observed
before or after time t. Although green can be given a definition in terms of
the locational predicates grue and bleen, this is irrelevant to the fact that
green meets the criterion for being a qualitative predicate whereas grue is
merely locational. He concludes that if some x's under examination—like
emeralds—satisfy both a qualitative and a locational predicate, but projecting
these two predicates yields conflicting predictions, namely, whether emeralds
examined after time t shall appear blue or green, we should project the
qualitative predicate, in this case green.
Carnap
Rudolf Carnap responded to Goodman's 1946
article. Carnap's approach to inductive logic is based on the notion of degree
of confirmation c(h,e) of a given hypothesis h by a given evidence e. Both h
and e are logical formulas expressed in a simple language L which allows for
multiple quantification ("for every x
there is a y such that ..."),
unary and binary predicate symbols
(properties and relations), and
an equality relation "=".
The universe of discourse consists of
denumerably many individuals, each of which is designated by its own constant
symbol; such individuals are meant to be regarded as positions ("like
space-time points in our actual world") rather than extended physical bodies.
A state description is a (usually infinite) conjunction containing every
possible ground atomic sentence, either negated or unnegated; such a
conjunction describes a possible state of the whole universe. Carnap requires
the following semantic properties:
Atomic sentences must be logically
independent of each other. In particular, different constant symbols must
designate different and entirely separate individuals. Moreover, different
predicates must be logically independent.
The qualities and relations designated by
the predicates must be simple, i.e. they must not be analyzable into simpler
components. Apparently, Carnap had in mind an irreflexive, partial, and
well-founded order is simpler than.
The set of primitive predicates in L must
be complete, i.e. every respect in which two positions in the universe may be
found to differ by direct observation, must be expressible in L.
Carnap distinguishes three kinds of
properties:
Purely qualitative properties; that is,
properties expressible without using individual constants, but not without
primitive predicates,
Purely positional properties; that is,
properties expressible without primitive predicates, and
Mixed properties; that is, all remaining
expressible properties.
To illuminate this taxonomy, let x be a
variable and a a constant symbol; then an example of 1. could be "x is
blue or x is non-warm", an example of 2. "x = a", and an example
of 3. "x is red and not x = a".
Based on his theory of inductive logic
sketched above, Carnap formalizes Goodman's notion of projectibility of a
property W as follows: the higher the relative frequency of W in an observed
sample, the higher is the probability that a non-observed individual has the
property W. Carnap suggests "as a tentative answer" to Goodman, that
all purely qualitative properties are projectible, all purely positional
properties are non-projectible, and mixed properties require further
investigation.
Quine
Willard Van Orman Quine discusses an
approach to consider only "natural kinds" as projectible predicates.
He first relates Goodman's grue paradox to Hempel's raven paradox by defining
two predicates F and G to be (simultaneously) projectible if all their shared
instances count toward confirmation of the claim "each F is a G".
Then Hempel's paradox just shows that the complements of projectible predicates
(such as "is a raven", and "is black") need not be
projectible, while Goodman's paradox shows that "is green" is projectible,
but "is grue" is not.
Next, Quine reduces projectibility to the
subjective notion of similarity. Two green emeralds are usually considered more
similar than two grue ones if only one of them is green. Observing a green
emerald makes us expect a similar observation (i.e., a green emerald) next
time. Green emeralds are a natural kind, but grue emeralds are not. Quine
investigates "the dubious scientific standing of a general notion of
similarity, or of kind". Both are basic to thought and language, like the
logical notions of e.g. identity, negation, disjunction. However, it remains
unclear how to relate the logical notions to similarity or kind; Quine
therefore tries to relate at least the latter two notions to each other.
Relation between similarity and kind
Assuming finitely many kinds only, the
notion of similarity can be defined by that of kind: an object A is more
similar to B than to C if A and B belong jointly to more kinds than A and C do.
Vice versa, it remains again unclear how to
define kind by similarity. Defining e.g. the kind of red things as the set of
all things that are more similar to a fixed "paradigmatical" red
object than this is to another fixed "foil" non-red object (cf. left
picture) isn't satisfactory, since the degree of overall similarity, including
e.g. shape, weight, will afford little evidence of degree of redness. (In the
picture, the yellow paprika might be considered more similar to the red one
than the orange.)
An alternative approach inspired by Carnap
defines a natural kind to be a set whose members are more similar to each other
than each non-member is to at least one member. However, Goodman argued, that this definition
would make the set of all red round things, red wooden things, and round wooden
things (cf. right picture) meet the proposed definition of a natural kind,
while "surely it is not what anyone means by a kind".
While neither of the notions of similarity
and kind can be defined by the other, they at least vary together: if A is
reassessed to be more similar to C than to B rather than the other way around,
the assignment of A, B, C to kinds will be permuted correspondingly; and
conversely.
Basic importance of similarity and kind
In language, every general term owes its
generality to some resemblance of the things referred to. Learning to use a
word depends on a double resemblance, viz. between the present and past
circumstances in which the word was used, and between the present and past
phonetic utterances of the word.
Every reasonable expectation depends on
resemblance of circumstances, together with our tendency to expect similar
causes to have similar effects. This includes any scientific experiment, since
it can be reproduced only under similar, but not under completely identical,
circumstances. Already Heraclitus' famous saying "No man ever steps in the
same river twice" highlighted the distinction between similar and
identical circumstances.
[show]Birds' similarity relations
Genesis of similarity and kind
In a behavioral sense, humans and other
animals have an innate standard of similarity. It is part of our animal
birthright, and characteristically animal in its lack of intellectual status,
e.g. its alieness to mathematics and logic, cf. bird example.
Induction itself is essentially animal
expectation or habit formation. Ostensive learning is a case of induction, and
a curiously comfortable one, since each man's spacing of qualities and kind is
enough like his neighbor's. In contrast, the "brute irrationality of our
sense of similarity" offers little reason to expect it being somehow in
tune with the unanimated nature, which we never made. Why inductively obtained
theories about it should be trusted is the perennial philosophical problem of
induction. Quine, following Watanabe, suggests Darwin 's theory as an explanation: if
people's innate spacing of qualities is a gene-linked trait, then the spacing that
has made for the most successful inductions will have tended to predominate
through natural selection. However, this cannot account for the human ability
to dynamically refine one's spacing of qualities in the course of getting
acquainted with a new area.
Similar predicates used in philosophical
analysis
Quus
In his book Wittgenstein on Rules and
Private Language, Saul Kripke proposed a related argument that leads to
skepticism about meaning rather than skepticism about induction, as part of his
personal interpretation (nicknamed "Kripkenstein" by some) of the
private language argument. He proposed a new form of addition, which he called
quus, which is identical with "+" in all cases except those in which
either of the numbers added are equal to or greater than 57; in which case the
answer would be 5, i.e.:
He then asks how, given certain obvious
circumstances, anyone could know that previously when I thought I had meant
"+", I had not actually meant quus. Kripke then argues for an
interpretation of Wittgenstein as holding that the meanings of words are not
individually contained mental entities.
Source From Wikipedia
没有评论:
发表评论