The knowledge argument (also known as
Mary's room or Mary the super-scientist) is a philosophical thought experiment
proposed by Frank Jackson in his article "Epiphenomenal Qualia"
(1982) and extended in "What Mary Didn't Know" (1986). The experiment
is intended to argue against physicalism—the view that the universe, including
all that is mental, is entirely physical. The debate that emerged following its
publication became the subject of an edited volume—There's Something About Mary
(2004)—which includes replies from such philosophers as Daniel Dennett, David
Lewis, and Paul Churchland.
Background
Mary's Room is a thought experiment that
attempts to establish that there are non-physical properties and attainable
knowledge that can be discovered only through conscious experience. It attempts
to refute the theory that all knowledge is physical knowledge. C. D. Broad,
Herbert Feigl, and Thomas Nagel, over a fifty-year span, presented insight to
the subject, which led to Jackson 's
proposed thought experiment. Broad makes the following remarks, describing a
thought experiment where an archangel has unlimited mathematical competences:
He would know exactly what the microscopic
structure of ammonia must be; but he would be totally unable to predict that a
substance with this structure must smell as ammonia does when it gets into the
human nose. The utmost that he could predict on this subject would be that
certain changes would take place in the mucous membrane, the olfactory nerves
and so on. But he could not possibly know that these changes would be
accompanied by the appearance of a smell in general or of the peculiar smell of
ammonia in particular, unless someone told him so or he had smelled it for
himself.
Roughly thirty years later, Feigl expresses
a similar notion. He concerns himself with a Martian, studying human behavior,
but lacking human sentiments. Feigl says:
...the Martian would be lacking completely
in the sort of imagery and empathy which depends on familiarity (direct
acquaintance) with the kinds of qualia to be imaged or empathized.
Nagel takes a slightly different approach.
In an effort to make his argument more adaptable and relatable, he takes the
stand of humans attempting to understand the sonar capabilities of bats. Even
with the entire physical database at one's fingertips, humans would not be able
to fully perceive or understand a bat's sonar system, namely what it is like to
perceive something with a bat's sonar.
Thought experiment
The thought experiment was originally
proposed by Frank Jackson as follows:
Mary is a brilliant scientist who is, for
whatever reason, forced to investigate the world from a black and white room
via a black and white television monitor. She specializes in the
neurophysiology of vision and acquires, let us suppose, all the physical
information there is to obtain about what goes on when we see ripe tomatoes, or
the sky, and use terms like "red", "blue", and so on. She
discovers, for example, just which wavelength combinations from the sky
stimulate the retina, and exactly how this produces via the central nervous
system the contraction of the vocal cords and expulsion of air from the lungs
that results in the uttering of the sentence "The sky is blue". [...]
What will happen when Mary is released from her black and white room or is given
a color television monitor? Will she learn anything or not?
In other words, Jackson 's Mary is a scientist who knows
everything there is to know about the science of color, but has never
experienced color. The question that Jackson
raises is: once she experiences color, does she learn anything new? Jackson claims that she
does.
There is disagreement about how to
summarize the premises and conclusion of the argument Jackson makes in this thought experiment.
Paul Churchland did so as follows:
Mary knows everything there is to know
about brain states and their properties.
It is not the case that Mary knows
everything there is to know about sensations and their properties.
Therefore, sensations and their properties
are not the same (≠) as the brain states and their properties.
However, Jackson objects that Churchland's formulation
is not his intended argument. He especially objects to the first premise of
Churchland's formulation: "The whole thrust of the knowledge argument is
that Mary (before her release) does not know everything there is to know about
brain states and their properties, because she does not know about certain
qualia associated with them. What is complete, according to the argument, is
her knowledge of matters physical." He suggests his preferred
interpretation:
Mary (before her release) knows everything
physical there is to know about other people.
Mary (before her release) does not know
everything there is to know about other people (because she learns something
about them on her release).
Therefore, there are truths about other
people (and herself) which escape the physicalist story.
Most authors who discuss the knowledge
argument cite the case of Mary, but Frank Jackson used a further example in his
seminal article: the case of a person, Fred, who sees a color unknown to normal
human perceivers.
Implications
Whether Mary learns something new upon
experiencing color has two major implications: the existence of qualia and the
knowledge argument against physicalism.
Qualia
First, if Mary does learn something new, it
shows that qualia (the subjective, qualitative properties of experiences,
conceived as wholly independent of behavior and disposition) exist. If Mary
gains something after she leaves the room — if she acquires knowledge of a
particular thing that she did not possess before — then that knowledge, Jackson
argues, is knowledge of the qualia of seeing red. Therefore, it must be
conceded that qualia are real properties, since there is a difference between a
person who has access to a particular quale and one who does not.
Refutation of physicalism
It seems just obvious that she will learn
something about the world and our visual experience of it. But then it is
inescapable that her previous knowledge was incomplete. But she had all the
physical information. Ergo there is more to have than that, and Physicalism is
false.
Epiphenomenalism
Explanatory completeness
of physiology + qualia
(Mary's room) = epiphenomenalism
Thus, at the conception of the thought
experiment, Jackson
was an epiphenomenalist.
Responses
Objections have been raised that have
required the argument to be refined. Doubters cite various holes in the thought
experiment that have arisen through critical examination.
Nemirow and Lewis present the "ability
hypothesis", and Conee argues for the "acquaintance hypothesis".
Both approaches attempt to demonstrate that Mary gains no new knowledge, but
instead gains something else. If she in fact gains no new propositional
knowledge, they contend, then what she does gain may be accounted for within
the physicalist framework. These are the two most notable objections to Jackson 's thought
experiment, and the claim it sets out to make.
Design of the thought experiment
Some have objected to Jackson 's argument on the grounds that the
scenario described in the thought experiment itself is not possible. For
example, Evan Thompson questioned the premise that Mary, simply by being
confined to a monochromatic environment, would not have any color experiences,
since she may be able to see color when dreaming, after rubbing her eyes, or in
afterimages from light perception. However, Graham and Horgan suggest that the
thought experiment can be refined to account for this: rather than situating
Mary in a black and white room, one might stipulate that she was unable to
experience color from birth, but was given this ability via medical procedure
later in life. Nida-Rümelin recognizes that one might question whether this
scenario would be possible given the science of color vision (although Graham
and Horgan suggest it is), but argues it is not clear that this matters to the
efficacy of the thought experiment, provided we can at least conceive of the
scenario taking place.
Objections have also been raised that, even
if Mary's environment were constructed as described in the thought experiment,
she would not, in fact, learn something new if she stepped out of her black and
white room to see the color red. Daniel Dennett asserts that if she already
truly knew "everything about color", that knowledge would necessarily
include a deep understanding of why and how human neurology causes us to sense
the "qualia" of color. Moreover, that knowledge would include the
ability to functionally differentiate between red and other colors. Mary would
therefore already know exactly what to expect of seeing red, before ever
leaving the room. Dennett argues that functional knowledge is identical to the
experience, with no ineffable 'qualia' left over. J. Christopher Maloney argues
similarly:
If, as the argument allows, Mary does
understand all that there is to know regarding the physical nature of colour
vision, she would be in a position to imagine what colour vision would be like.
It would be like being in physical state Sk, and Mary knows all about such
physical states. Of course, she herself has not been in Sk, but that is no bar
to her knowing what it would be like to be in Sk. For she, unlike us, can describe the
nomic relations between Sk and other states of chromatic vision...Give her a
precise description in the notation of neurophysiology of a colour vision
state, and she will very likely be able to imagine what such a state would be
like.
Surveying the literature on Jackson 's argument, Nida-Rümelin identifies, however, that
many simply doubt the claim that Mary would not gain new knowledge upon leaving
the room, including physicalists who do not agree with Jackson 's conclusions. Most cannot help but
admit that "new information or knowledge comes her way after
confinement," enough that this view "deserves to be described as the
received physicalist view of the Knowledge Argument." Some philosophers
have also objected to Jackson 's
first premise by arguing that Mary could not know all the physical facts about
color vision prior to leaving the room. Owen Flanagan argues that Jackson 's thought
experiment "is easy to defeat," He grants that "Mary knows
everything about color vision that can be expressed in the vocabularies of a
complete physics, chemistry, and neuroscience," and then distinguishes
between "metaphysical physicalism" and "linguistic
physicalism":
Metaphysical physicalism simply asserts
that what there is, and all there is, is physical stuff and its relations.
Linguistic physicalism is the thesis that everything physical can be expressed
or captured in the languages of the basic sciences…Linguistic physicalism is
stronger than metaphysical physicalism and less plausible.
Flanagan argues that, while Mary has all
the facts that are expressible in "explicitly physical language," she
can only be said to have all the facts if one accepts linguistic physicalism. A
metaphysical physicalist can simply deny linguistic physicalism and hold that
Mary's learning what seeing red is like, though it cannot be expressed in
language, is nevertheless a fact about the physical world, since the physical
is all that exists. Similarly to Flanagan, Torin Alter contends that Jackson
conflates physical facts with "discursively learnable" facts, without
justification:
…some facts
about conscious experiences of various kinds cannot be learned through purely
discursive means. This, however, does not yet license any further conclusions
about the nature of the experiences that these discursively unlearnable facts
are about. In particular, it does not entitle us to infer that these
experiences are not physical events.
Nida-Rümelin argues in response to such
views that it is "hard to understand what it is for a property or a fact
to be physical once we drop the assumption that physical properties and
physical facts are just those properties and facts that can be expressed in
physical terminology."
Ability hypothesis
Several objections to Jackson have been raised on the grounds that
Mary does not gain new factual knowledge when she leaves the room, but rather a
new ability. Nemirow claims that "knowing what an experience is like is
the same as knowing how to imagine having the experience". He argues that
Mary only obtained the ability to do something, not the knowledge of something
new. Lewis put forth a similar argument, claiming that Mary gained an ability
to "remember, imagine and recognize." In the response to Jackson's
knowledge argument, they both agree that someone makes a genuine discovery when
she sees red for the first time, but deny her discovery involves coming to know
some facts of which she was not already cognizant before her release.
Therefore, what she obtained is a discovery of new abilities rather than new
facts; her discovery of what it is like to experience color consists merely in
her gaining new ability of how to do certain things, but not gaining new
factual knowledge. In light of such considerations, Churchland distinguishes
between two senses of knowing, "knowing how" and "knowing
that", where knowing how refers to abilities and knowing that refers to
knowledge of facts. He aims to reinforce this line of objection by appealing to
the different locations in which each type of knowledge is represented in the
brain, arguing that there is a true, demonstratively physical distinction
between them.
In response, Levin argues that a novel color
experience does in fact yield new factual knowledge, such as "information
about the color's similarities and compatibilities with other colors, and its
effect on other of our mental states." Tye counters that Mary could have
(and would have, given the stipulations of the thought experiment) learned all
such facts prior to leaving the room, without needing to experience the color
firsthand. For example, Mary could know the fact "red is more like orange
than green" without ever experiencing the colors in question.
Earl Conee objects that having an ability
to imagine seeing a color is neither necessary nor sufficient for knowing what
it is like to see that color, meaning the ability hypothesis does not capture
the nature of the new knowledge Mary acquires upon leaving the room. To show
that ability is not necessary, Conee cites the example of someone who is able
to see colors when she is looking at them, but who lacks the capacity to
imagine colors when she is not. He argues that while staring at something that
looks red to her, she would have knowledge of what it is like to see red, even
though she lacks the ability to imagine what it is like. In order to show
precisely that imaginative abilities are not sufficient for knowing what it is
like, Conee introduces the following example: Martha, "who is highly
skilled at visualizing an intermediate shade that she has not experienced
between pairs of shades that she has experienced...happens not to have any
familiarity with the shade known as cherry red". Martha has been told that
cherry red is exactly midway between burgundy red and fire red (she has
experienced these two shades of red, but not cherry). With this, Martha has the
ability to imagine cherry red if she so chooses, but as long as she does not exercise
this ability, to imagine cherry red, she does not know what it is like to see
cherry red.
One might accept Conee's arguments that
imaginative ability is neither necessary nor sufficient for knowing what it is
like to see a color, but preserve a version of the ability hypothesis that
employs an ability other than imagination. For example, Gertler discusses the
option that what Mary gains is not an ability to imagine colors, but an ability
to recognize colors by their phenomenal quality.
Acquaintance hypothesis
Due to his dissatisfaction with the ability
hypothesis, Earl Conee presents another variant. Conee's acquaintance
hypothesis identifies a third category of knowledge, "knowledge by
acquaintance of an experience," that is not reducible to factual knowledge
nor to knowing-how. He argues that the knowledge Mary actually acquires
post-release is acquaintance knowledge. Knowing an experience by acquaintance
"requires the person to be familiar with the known entity in the most
direct way that it is possible for a person to be aware of that thing".
Since "experiencing a quality is the most direct way to apprehend a
quality," Mary gains acquaintance with color qualia after release. Conee
thus defends himself against the knowledge argument like this:
Qualia are physical properties of
experiences (and experiences are physical processes). Let Q be such a property.
Mary can know all about Q and she can know
that a given experience has Q before release, although — before release — she
is not acquainted with Q.
After release Mary gets acquainted with Q,
but she does not acquire any new item of propositional knowledge by getting
acquainted with Q (in particular she already knew under what conditions normal
perceivers have experiences with the property Q).
Tye also defends a version of the
acquaintance hypothesis that he compares to Conee's, though he clarifies that
acquaintance with a color should not be equated to applying a concept to one's
color experience.
In Conee's account, one can come to know
(be acquainted with) a phenomenal quality only by experiencing it, but not by
knowing facts about it as Mary did. This is different from other physical
objects of knowledge: one comes to know a city, for example, simply by knowing
facts about it. Gertler uses this disparity to oppose Conee's account: a
dualist who posits the existence of qualia has a way of explaining it, with
reference to qualia as different entities than physical objects; while Conee
describes the disparity, Gertler argues that his physicalist account does
nothing to explain it.
The neural basis of qualia
V.S. Ramachandran and Edward Hubbard of the
Center for Brain and Cognition at UCSD argue that Mary might do one of three
things upon seeing a red apple for the first time:
Mary says she sees nothing but gray.
She has the "Wow!" response from
subjectively experiencing the color for the first time.
She experiences a form of blindsight for
color, in which she reports seeing no difference between a red apple and an
apple painted gray, but when asked to point to the red apple, she correctly
does.
They explain further: "Which of these
three possible outcomes will actually occur? We believe we've learned the
answer from a colorblind synesthete subject. Much like the theoretical Mary, our
colorblind synesthete volunteer can not see certain hues, because of deficient
color receptors. However, when he looks at numbers, his synesthesia enables him
to experience colors in his mind that he has never seen in the real world. He
calls these "Martian colors." The fact that color cells (and
corresponding colors) can activate in his brain helps us answer the
philosophical question: we suggest that the same thing will happen to
Mary."
Ramachandran and Hubbard's contribution is
in terms of exploring "the neural basis of qualia" by "using
pre-existing, stable differences in the conscious experiences of people who
experience synaesthesia compared with those who do not" but, they note
that "this still doesn't explain why these particular events are qualia
laden and others are not (Chalmers' 'hard problem') but at least it narrows the
scope of the problem" (p. 25).
Dualist responses
Jackson himself went on to reject
epiphenomenalism, and dualism altogether. He argues that, because when Mary
first sees red, she says "wow", it must be Mary's qualia that causes
her to say "wow". This contradicts epiphenomenalism because it
involves a conscious state causing an overt speech behavior. Since the Mary's
room thought experiment seems to create this contradiction, there must be something
wrong with it. Jackson
now believes that the physicalist approach (from a perspective of indirect
realism) provides the better explanation. In contrast to epiphenominalism, Jackson says that the
experience of red is entirely contained in the brain, and the experience
immediately causes further changes in the brain (e.g. creating memories). This
is more consilient with neuroscience's understanding of color vision. Jackson suggests that
Mary is simply discovering a new way for her brain to represent qualities that
exist in the world. In a similar argument, philosopher Philip Pettit likens the
case of Mary to patients suffering from akinetopsia, the inability to perceive
the motion of objects. If someone were raised in a stroboscopic room and
subsequently 'cured' of the akinetopsia, they would not be surprised to
discover any new facts about the world (they do, in fact, know that objects
move). Instead, their surprise would come from their brain now allowing them to
see this motion.
Despite a lack of dualist responses overall
and Jackson 's
own change of view, there are more recent instances of prominent dualists
defending the Knowledge Argument. David Chalmers, one of the most prominent
contemporary dualists, considers Jackson 's
thought experiment to successfully show that materialism is false. Chalmers
considers responses along the lines of the "ability hypothesis"
objection (described above) to be the most promising objections, but
unsuccessful: even if Mary does gain a new ability to imagine or recognize
colors, she would also necessarily gain factual knowledge about the colors she
now sees, such as the fact of how the experience of seeing red relates to the
physical brain states underlying it. He also considers arguments that knowledge
of what it is like to see red and of the underlying physical mechanisms are
actually knowledge of the same fact, just under a different "mode of
presentation," meaning Mary did not truly gain new factual knowledge.
Chalmers rejects these, arguing that Mary still necessarily gains new factual
knowledge about how the experience and the physical processes relate to one
another, i.e. a fact about exactly what kind of experience is caused by those
processes. Nida-Rümelin defends a complex, though similar, view, involving properties
of experience she calls "phenomenal properties."
Source From Wikipedia
没有评论:
发表评论